Mark Skousen, ed.
Dissent on Keynes:
A Critical Appraisal of Keynesian Economics
New York: Praeger Publishers, 1992, pp. 131-147
Is Milton Friedman a Keynesian?
Roger W. Garrison
He Isn't
But He Is
There is a story about a young job candidate interviewing for an entry-level
position in the geography department of a state university. One senior
faculty member, whose opinion of our modern educational system was not
especially high, asked the simple question, "Which way does the Mississippi
River run?" In ignorance of the biases of this particular geography department
and in fear of jeopardizing his employment prospects, the candidate boldly
replied, "I can teach it either way."
When the question "Is Milton
Friedman a Keynesian?" was first suggested to me as a topic, I couldn't
help but think of the uncommitted geographer. But in this case, opposing
answers can be defended with no loss of academic respectability. When teaching
at the sophomore level to students who are hearing the names "Keynes" and
"Friedman" for the first time, I provide the conventional contrast that
emerges naturally out of the standard account of the "Keynesian Revolution"
and the "Monetarist Counter-Revolution." To claim otherwise would come
close to committing academic malpractice. Either a casual survey or a careful
study of the writings of Keynes and Friedman reveals many issues on which
these two theorists are poles apart.
Yet, one can make the claim
that Friedman is a Keynesian and remain in good scholarly company. Both
Don Patinkin (Gordon, 1974) and Harry Johnson (1971) see Friedman's monetary
theory as an extension of the ideas commonly associated with Keynes. Some
of their arguments, however, run counter to those of the Austrian school,
which serves as a basis for this chapter. And while Friedman, by his own
account, was quoted out of context as saying, "We're all Keynesians now,"
his in-context statement is thoroughly consistent with an Austrian assessment.
More than two decades ago, during an interview with a reporter from Time
magazine, Friedman commented that "in one sense, we are all Keynesians
now; in another, no one is a Keynesian any longer." The two senses were
identified in his subsequent elaboration: "We all use the Keynesian language
and apparatus; none of us any longer accepts the initial Keynesian conclusions"
(Friedman 1968b, p. 15).
Patinkin and Johnson have
each argued that Friedman's attention to the demand for money, and particularly
his inclusion of the rate of interest as one of the determinants of money
demand, puts him closer to Keynes than to the pre-Keynesian monetary theorists.
Friedman has responded by insisting that the inclusion of the interest
rate in the money-demand function is a minor feature of his theoretical
framework (Gordon, 1974, p. 159). Austrian monetary theorists, who pay
more attention to the interest rate than does Friedman and as much attention
to it as did Keynes, have a different perspective on the interest-rate
issue. Both Keynes and Friedman have neglected the effects of change in
the interest rate on the economy's structure of capital. From an Austrian
viewpoint this sin of omission, which derives from a common "language and
apparatus," makes both Keynesianism and Monetarism subject to the same
Austrian critique.
Keynesianism: From the Treatise to the General Theory
It is important to note, then, that the sense in which the statement
"We're all Keynesians now" is true�from both a Monetarist and an Austrian
perspective�involves a circumscribed "all." Monetarists are included; Austrians
are not. Drawing out the essential differences among these schools of thought
requires that we begin by considering the common "language and apparatus"
that predates Friedman's (1969a) restatement of the quantity theory of
money and that predates even Keynes's General Theory. The Austrians
can be identified as Keynesian dissenters on the basis of Keynes's earliest
macroeconomics.
Keynes's two-volume Treatise
on Money, which appeared in 1930, was not well received by economists
who drew their inspiration from Carl Menger and Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk.
Although the macroeconomics found in Keynes's Treatise is not readily
recognizable today as Keynesian theory, the theoretical building blocks
and methods of construction are largely the same. The macroeconomic aggregates
of saving, investment, and output are played off against one another in
a manner that establishes equilibrium values for the interest rate and
price level.
In an extended critique
of this early rendition of Keynesianism, F. A. Hayek found many inconsistencies
and ambiguities, but his most fundamental dissatisfaction derived from
Keynes's mode of theorizing�from his "language and apparatus": "Mr. Keynes's
aggregates conceal the most fundamental mechanisms of change" (Hayek, 1931a:
p. 227). Keynes had argued that changes in the rate of interest have no
significant effect on the rate of profit for the investment sector as a
whole. Hayek's point was that profit reckoned on a sector-wide basis is
not a significant part of the market mechanism that governs production
activity. A change in the rate of interest means that profit prospects
for some industries rise, while profit prospects for others fall. The systematic
differences in profits rates among industries, and not the average or aggregate
of those rates, are what constitute the relevant "mechanisms of change."
There were fundamental shifts
in Keynes's thinking during the six years between his Treatise and
his General Theory, but none that could be considered responsive
to Hayek's critique. In the General Theory, impenetrable uncertainty
about the future clouded the decision processes of investors and wealth
holders; the interest rate became a product of convention and psychology,
largely if not wholly detached from economic reality; changes in market
conditions were accommodated by income adjustments rather than price or
interest-rate adjustments; and unemployment equilibrium became the normal
state of affairs.
Selective readings of what
Keynes actually wrote�as well as creative readings of what he may have
intended to write�have given rise to conflicting interpretations of Keynes's
message. In many instances, disagreements about Keynesian answers to macroeconomic
questions derive from disagreements about what the relevant macroeconomic
questions are. Is Keynes asking: How, in particular, do markets actually
work? Or is he asking: Why, in general, do they not work well? More specifically,
does the interest-inelastic demand for investment funds enter importantly
into his theory, or does the instability of investment demand, driven as
it is by the "animal spirts" of the business world, swamp any consideration
of interest inelasticity? Does the highly interest-elastic demand for money
enter importantly into his theory, or does the instability of money demand,
based as it is on the "fetish of liquidity," swamp any consideration of
interest elasticity?
Interpreters such as G.
L. S. Shackle (1974) and Ludwig M. Lachmann (1986, pp. 89-100 and passim),
who focus on the pervasive uncertainty that enshrouds the future and the
utter baselessness of long-term expectations, impute great significance
to the animal spirts, as they affect the bulls and bears in investment
markets, and to the fetish of liquidity, as it affects their willingness
to make a commitment to either side of any market. Wealth holders are sometimes
more willing, sometimes less willing, to part with liquidity; speculators
are sometimes bullish, sometimes bearish, in their investment decisions.
Such behavior gives rise to continuously changing market conditions and
to a continuously changing pattern of prices. The sequential patterns of
prices in a market economy, predictable by neither economist nor entrepreneur,
are likened to the sequential patterns of cut glass in a kaleidoscope.
There certainly is no reason
to expect, in this vision of the market process, that prices, wage rates,
and interest rates will be consistent with the coordination of production
activities over time or even that they will be consistent with the full
employment of labor at any one point in time. "Keynesian Kaleidics," as
this strand of Keynesianism is sometimes called, is not so much a particular
understanding of the operation of a market economy as a denial that any
such understanding is possible. Clearly, Friedman is not a Keynesian in
this sense.
Interpreters such as John
Hicks (1937) and Alvin Hansen (1947), whose focus penetrated Keynes's cloud
of uncertainty, have identified a set of behavioral relationships which,
together with the corresponding equilibrium conditions, imply determinate
values of total income and the interest rate.(1)
In the most elementary formulation, net investment (I) must equal net saving
(S), and the demand for liquidity (L) must be accommodated by the supply
of money (M). This ISLM framework, more broadly called income-expenditure
analysis, has in many quarters�but not in Austrian ones�come to be thought
of as the analytical apparatus common to all macroeconomic theories. Appropriate
assumptions about the stability of investment and money demand, interest
elasticities, and price and wage rigidities allow for the derivations of
either Keynesian or Monetarist conclusions.
Friedman vs. Keynes
Within the context of income-expenditure analysis, it is appropriate
to think of Friedman's Monetarism as being directly opposed to Keynesianism.
Although both Keynesianism and Monetarists accept the same high level of
aggregation, one which closes off issues believed by the Austrians to be
among the most important, they have sharp disagreements about the nature
of the relationships among these macroeconomic aggregates. Several such
disagreements, many as reported or implied by Friedman (1970), are included
in the following list.
1. Keynesians believe that the interest rate, largely, if not wholly,
a monetary phenomenon, is determined by the supply of and demand for money.
Monetarists believe that the interest rate, largely a real phenomenon,
is determined by the supply of and demand for loanable funds, a market
which faithfully reflects actual opportunities and constraints in the investment
sector.
2. In the Keynesian vision, a change in the interest rate has little
effect on (aggregate) investment; in the Monetarist vision, a change in
the interest rate has a substantial effect on (aggregate) investment. This
difference reflects, in large part, the short-run orientation of Keynesians
and the long-run orientation of Monetarists.
3. Keynesians conceive of a narrowly channeled mechanism through which
monetary policy affects national income. Specifically, money creation lowers
the interest rate, which stimulates investment and hence employment, which,
in turn, give rise to multiple rounds of increased spending and increased
real income. The nearly exclusive focus on this particular channel of effects,
together with the belief that investment demand is interest-inelastic,
accounts for the Keynesian preference for fiscal policy over monetary policy
as a means of stimulating or retarding economic activity. Government spending
has a direct effect on the level of employment; money creation has only
an indirect and weak effect. Monetarists conceive of an extremely broad-based
market mechanism through which money creation stimulates spending in all
directions�on old as well as new investment goods, on real as well as financial
assets, on consumption goods as well as investment goods. Nominal incomes
are higher all around as a direct result of money creation, but with a
stable demand for money in real terms, the price level increases in direct
proportion to nominal money growth so that real incomes are unaffected.
4. Keynesians believe that long-run expectations, which have no basis
in reality in any case, are subject to unexpected change. Economic prosperity
is based on baseless optimism; economic depression, on baseless pessimism.
Monetarists believe that profit expectations reflect, by and large, consumer
preferences, resource constraints, and technological factors as they actually
exist.
5. Keynesians believe that economic downturns are attributable to instabilities
characteristic of a market economy. A sudden collapse in the demand for
investment funds, triggered by an irrational and unexplainable loss of
confidence in the business community, is followed by multiple rounds of
decreased spending and income. Monetarists believe that economic downturns
are attributable to inept or misguided monetary policy. And unwarranted
monetary contraction puts downward pressure on incomes and on the level
of output during the period in which nominal wages and prices are adjusting
to the smaller money supply.
6. Keynesians believe that in conditions of economy-wide unemployment,
idle factories, and unsold merchandise, price and wages will not adjust
downward to their market-clearing levels�or that they will not adjust quickly
enough, or that the market process through which such adjustments are made
works perversely as falling prices and falling wages feed on one another.
Monetarists do not believe that such perversities, if they exist at all,
play a significant role in the market process. They believe instead that
prices and wages can and will adjust to market conditions. The fact that
such adjustments are neither perfect nor instantaneous is, in the Monetarists'
judgment, no basis for advocating governmental intervention. A market process
that adjusts prices and wages to existing market conditions is preferable
to a government policy that attempts to adjust market conditions to existing
prices and wages.
An Austrian Perspective on the Common Language and Apparatus
The contrast between Keynesianism, as interpreted by Hicks and Hansen,
and Monetarism, as outlined by Friedman (Gordon 1974), is based upon their
common analytical framework. The recognition of this common framework underlies
the assessment by Gerald P. O'Driscoll and Sudha R. Shenoy (1976, p. 191)
that "Monetarism... does not differ in its fundamental approach from the
other dominant branch of macroeconomics, that of Keynesianism."(2)
But the Keynesian/Monetarist income-expenditure analysis, no less than
the analysis in Keynes's Treatise on Money, is subject to Hayek's
early criticism. The aggregates conceal the most fundamental mechanisms
of change. While many of the conflicting claims can be reconciled in terms
of the short-run and long-run orientation of Keynesians and Monetarists,
respectively, and in terms of their contrasting philosophical orientations,
neither vision takes into account the workings of failings of the market
mechanisms within the investment aggregate.
Austrian macroeconomics(3)
is set apart from both Keynesianism and Monetarism by its attention to
the differential effects of interest rate changes within the investment
sector, or�using the Austrian terminology�within the economy's structure
of production. A fall in the rate of interest, for instance, brings about
systematic changes in the structure of production. A lower interest rate
favor production for the more distant future over production for the more
immediate future; it favors relatively more time-consuming or roundabout
methods of production as well as the production and use of more durable
capital equipment. The "mechanisms of change" activated by a fall in the
interest rate consist of profit differentials among the different stages
of production. The market process that eliminates these differentials reallocates
resources away from the later stages of production and into the earlier
stages; it gives the intertemporal structure of production more of a future
orientation.
The ultimate consequence
of this capital restructuring brought about by a decrease in the rate of
interest depends fundamentally upon the basis for the decrease. If the
lower rate of interest is a reflection of an increased willingness to save
on the part of market participants, then the capital restructuring serves
to retailor the production process to fit the new intertemporal preferences.
Continual restructuring of this sort�along with technological advancement�is
the essence of economic growth. If, however, the lower rate of interest
is brought about by an injection of newly created money through credit
markets, then the capital restructuring, which is at odds with the intertemporal
preferences of market participants, will necessarily be ill-fated. The
period marked by the extension of artificially cheap credit is followed
by a period of high interest rates when cumulative demands for credit have
outstripped genuine saving. The artificial, credit-induced boom will necessarily
end in a bust.
The Austrian theory of the
business cycle identifies the market process that turns an artificial boom
into a bust. The misallocation of resources within the investment sector
requires a subsequent liquidation and reallocation. The more extensive
the misallocation, the more disruptive the liquidation. After the prolonged
period of cheap credit during the 1920s, for instance, a substantial reallocation
of capital from relatively long-term projects to relatively short-term
ones was essential for the restoration of economic health. A higher than
normal level of unemployment characterized the period during which workers
who lost their jobs in the over capitalized sectors of the economy were
absorbed into other sectors.(4)
Accounting for the artificial
boom and the consequent bust is no part of Keynesian income-expenditure
analysis, nor is it an integral part of Monetarist analysis. The absence
of any significant relationship between boom and bust is an inevitable
result of dealing with the investment sector in aggregate terms. The analytical
oversight derives from theoretical formulation in Keynesian analysis and
from empirical observation in Monetarist analysis. But from an Austrian
perspective, the differences in method and substance are outweighed by
the common implication of Keynesianism and Monetarism, namely that there
is no boom-bust cycle of any macroeconomic significance.
In the General Theory,
the interest rate is sometimes treated as if it depends on monetary considerations
alone, such as in Chapter 14, where Keynes contrasts his own theory of
interest with the classical theory. The supply of and demand for money
(alone) determine the equilibrium rate of interest, which in turn determines
the level of investment and hence the level of employment. The essentially
one-way chain of determinacy makes no allowance for the pattern of saving
and investment decisions to have any effect upon the rate of interest While
this rarified version of Keynesian macroeconomics has not survived the
translation from the General Theory to modern textbooks, it can
by easily represented as a special case of the ISLM construction, one in
which the LM curve is a horizontal line that moves up or down with changes
either in liquidity preferences or in the supply of money. Using more formal
terminology, the system of equations is recursive, such that the rate of
interest can be determined independently of the other endogenous variables.
Within this framework, there is simply no scope for a boom-bust cycle as
envisioned by the Austrians.
In the more general ISLM
framework, the rate of interest and the levels of investment, saving, and
income are determined simultaneously rather than sequentially, but Keynes
downplays any cyclical movements in these magnitudes that might result
from the two-way chains of causation. He emphasizes instead the possibility
of economic stagnation�of enduring secular unemployment. In Chapter 18
of the General Theory, his stocktaking chapter, Keynes envisions
an economy in which there are minor fluctuations of income�and hence
of employment�around a level of income substantially below the economy's
full-employment potential. Only in his "Short Notes Suggested by the General
Theory" does Keynes attempt to account for the cyclical fluctuations considered
inherent in the nature of capitalism. The crises, or upper turning point,
is caused by a change in long-term profit expectations that motivate the
business community�expectations that are "based on shifting and unreliable
evidence" and are "subject to sudden and violent changes" (Keynes, 1936,
p. 315). The recovery, or lower turning point, is governed by the durability
of the capital in existence at the time of the crisis. But in the Keynesian
vision, the economy recovers only to some equilibrium level of unemployment,
not to its full-employment potential.(5)
More tellingly, Keynes perceives
a one-way chain of causation from money supply as a policy variable to
investment (and hence employment) as a policy goal. The monetary authority
increases the money supply; the interest rate falls until money demand
exhausts supply; investment increases, as does employment. A new equilibrium
is established in which the rate of interest is permanently lower and the
levels of investment and employment are permanently higher. In the income-expenditure
framework, the temporal pattern of investment does not enter into the analysis,
and the distinction between a genuine boom and an artificial boom is itself
an artificial distinction.
Friedman's Plucking Model
Keynesian analysis does not disprove the Austrian idea that a credit-induced
boom leads to a bust. By adopting a higher level of aggregation, it simply
fails to bring this issue into focus. Nor is the Austrian idea disproved
by the Monetarists, who rely on a highly aggregated statistical analysis
for clues about the relationship between booms and busts. Levels of aggregate
output that characterize a typical downturn do not correlate well with
a preceding upturn, but the magnitude of the downturn does seem to be related
to the magnitude of the succeeding upturn. In the Monetarists' empirical
analysis, there appears to be a bust-boom, rather than a boom-bust cycle.
Friedman (1969b, pp. 27-277)
has offered what he calls a "plucking model" of the economy's output over
the period 1879-1961.(6) Imagine a string
glued to the underside of an inclined plane. The degree of incline represents
long-run secular growth in output. If the string were glued at every point
along the inclined plane, it would represent an economy with no cyclical
problems at all. Cyclical problems of the type actually experienced can
be represented by plucking the string downward at random intervals along
the inclined plane. In this representation of the economy's actual growth
path, the economic process that gives us healthy secular growth occasionally
comes "unglued." While the consequent sagging of economic performance is
unrelated to the previous growth, recovery to the potential growth path
is necessarily related to the extent of the sag. But for the slight degree
of incline, there would be a one-to-one relationship between downturn and
subsequent recovery.
On the basis of this Monetarist
representation, the Austrian ideas are rejected, not so much on the basis
of the answers offered, but on the basis of the questions asked. What is
the market process that turns a boom into a bust? There is no empirical
evidence that suggests any such process to be at work. What is the market
process that turns a slump into a recovery? This is the empirically relevant
question, in the Monetarists' view. The suggested answer, which has the
flavor of textbook Keynesianism, involves the conventional operation of
market forces in the face of institutional price and wage rigidities (Ibid.,
p. 274).
As Friedman clearly recognizes,
the dismissal of the possibility of a boom-bust cycle and the empirical
identification of the bust-boom cycle both derive from the inherent asymmetry
of deviations from the potential growth path. The economy's output can
fall significantly below its potential level, but it cannot rise significantly
above it. The fact that Friedman's formulation is in terms of aggregate
output, however, suggests that the Austrian critique of early Keynesianism
is equally applicable to modern Monetarism: Professor Friedman's aggregates
conceal the most fundamental mechanisms of change.
The economy's output consists
in the output of consumer goods plus the output of investment goods. An
artificially low rate of interest can shift resources away from the former
category and into the latter. More importantly, it can skew the pattern
of investment activities toward production for the more distant future;
it can overcommit the investment sector to relatively long-term projects.
Such money-induced distortions are wholly consistent with the changes in
aggregate
output over the nine-decade period studied by Friedman.
In terms of the plucking
model, the Monetarists observe that some segments of the string are glued
fast to the inclined plane and other segments are not. But in terms of
their macroeconomic aggregates, there is nothing in the nature of the string�or
the glue�as we move along a glued section toward an unglued one that explains
why the glue fails. Monetarists instead conceive of the string as plucked
down by some force (an inept central bank) that is at work only on the
segments that constitute the downturn. The Austrians, working at a lower
level of aggregation, examine the makeup of the string (the allocation
of resources within the investment sector) and the consistency of the glue
(the rate on interest and pattern of prices upon which resource allocation
has been based during the boom). They conclude that if the interest rate
has been held artificially low by monetary expansion, the intertemporal
allocation of resources is inconsistent with actual intertemporal preferences
and resource availabilities. The string is destined to become unglued.
Contrasting Theories of Interest
Friedman's plucking model is more notable for the aspects of the market
process it ignores than for the general movements of macroeconomic aggregates
it represents. Movements in the rate of interest and consequences of those
movements for the allocation of resources within the macroeconomic aggregates
play no role in either Monetarism or Keynesianism. In fact, the very choice
of a particular level of aggregation reflects a judgment about which aspects
of the market process are significant enough to be included in macroeconomic
theory. Relationships between the aggregates are significant; relationships
within
the aggregates are not. The aggregates chosen by Keynes were accepted by
Friedman, indicating that the two theorists made the same judgment in this
regard.
Their bases for judgment,
however, are not the same. Opposing views about the nature and significance
of the rate of interest and of changes in that rate underlie the decisions
by Keynes and Friedman to neglect the considerations that are so dominant
in Austrian macroeconomics. All three views can be identified in terms
of the interest-rate dynamics first spelled out by the Swedish economist
Knut Wicksell. The natural rate of interest, so called by Wicksell,
is the rate consistent with the economy's capital structure and resource
base. If allowed to prevail, it would maintain an equilibrium between saving
and investment�and would also keep constant the general level of prices.
The bank rate of interest, by contrast, is a direct result of bank
policy. Credit expansion lowers the bank rate; credit contraction raises
it. Macroeconomic equilibrium can be maintained, according to Wicksell,
only by a monetary policy that keeps the bank rate equal to the natural
rate.(7) Therefore, a banking system that
pursues a cheap-credit policy (by holding the bank rate of interest below
the natural rate) throws the economy into macroeconomic disequilibrium.
While the Austrians, beginning
with Mises (1971), adopted Wicksell's formulation as the basis for their
own theorizing, deviating from it only in terms of the consequences of
a credit-induced macroeconomic disequilibrium, neither Keynesians no Monetarists
share Wicksell's concern about the relationship between the bank rate and
the natural rate. In summary terms, Keynes denied that the concept of the
natural rate had any significance; Friedman, who accepts the concept, denies
that there can be deviations of any significance from the natural rate.
Although Keynes had incorporated
a modified version of Wicksell's natural rate in his Treatise on Money,
he could find no place for it in his General Theory. In the earlier
work, full employment was the norm; and the (natural) rate of interest
kept investment in line with available saving. In the later work, the rate
of interest is determined, in conjunction with the supply of money, by
irrational psychology (the fetish of liquidity), and the level of employment
accommodates itself to that interest rate. Keynes argued that " there is
... a different natural rate of interest for each hypothetical level
of employment" and concluded that "the concept of the 'natural' rate of
interest ... has [nothing] very useful or significant to contribute to
our analysis" (Keynes 1936, pp. 242-43).
In Friedman's Monetatism,
competition in labor markets gives rise to a market-clearing wage rate,
which singles out from Keynes's hypothetical levels of employment the one
level for which labor supply is equal to labor demand. The concept of the
natural rate of interest, that is, the rate that clears the loan market
and keeps investment in line with savings, fits as naturally into the Monetarists'
thinking as it fits into Wicksell's. In fact, Friedman coined the term
"natural rate of unemployment" to exploit the similarity between the Wicksellian
analysis of the loan market and his own analysis of the labor market (Friedman,
1976, p. 228). According to Wicksell, a discrepancy between the bank and
the natural rates of interest gives rise to a corresponding discrepancy
between
saving and investment; according to Friedman, a discrepancy between the
actual and the natural rates of unemployment reflects a corresponding discrepancy
between the real wage rate, as perceived by employers, and the real wage
rate, as perceived by employees. Macroeconomic disequilibrium plays itself
out in ways that eventually eliminate such discrepancies in loan markets
(for Wicksell) and in labor markets (for Friedman).
While the Wickesll-styled
dynamics in labor markets have been of some concern to Monetarists, the
corresponding loan-market dynamics play no role at all in Monetarism. The
bank rate of interest never deviates from the natural rate for long enough
to have any significant macroeconomic consequences. Whatever effects there
are of minor and short-lived deviations are trivialized by Friedman as
"first-round effects" (Gordon, 1974, pp. 146-48). That is, the initial
lending of money, the first round, is trivial in comparison to the subsequent
rounds of spending, which may number twenty-five to thirty per year. Friedman
summarily dismisses all such interest-rate effects, as spelled out by modern
Keynesians (Tobin) and by Austrians (Mises), and affirms that his own macroeconomics
is characterized by its according "almost no importance to first-round
effects" (Ibid., p 147).
Austrian macroeconomics
is distinguished from the macroeconomics of both Keynes and Friedman by
its acceptance of the Wicksellian concept of the natural rate and by its
attention to the consequences of a bank-rate deviating from the natural
rate. It is distinguished from Wicksellian macroeconomics, however, in
terms of the particular consequences taken to be most relevant. For Wicksell
(1936, pp. 39-40 and passim), a deviation between the two rates
puts upward pressure on the general level of prices. If, for instance,
the natural rate rises as a result of technological developments, inflation
will persist until the bank rate is adjusted upward. A relatively low bank
rate may create "tendencies" for capital to be reallocated in ways not
consistent with the natural rate, but those tendencies do not, in Wicksell's
formal analysis, become actualities. Real factors continue to govern the
allocation of capital, while bank policy affects only the general level
of prices (Ibid., pp. 90 and 143-44). But because both the Swedish
and the Austrian formulations are based upon Böhm-Bawerkian capital
theory, the particular "tendencies" identified by Wicksell correspond closely
to the most relevant "mechanisms of change" spelled out by Hayek. Also,
Wicksell's informal discussion, which accompanies his formal exposition,
gives greater scope for actual quantity adjustments within the capital
structure (Ibid., pp. 89-92).
For the Austrians, the effects
of a cheap-credit policy on the general level of prices is, at best, of
secondary importance. If in fact the discrepancy between the two rates
of interest is attributable to technological developments, as Wicksell
believed it to be (Ibid., p. 118), then the resulting increase in
the economy's real output would put downward pressure on prices, largely,
if not wholly, offsetting the effect of the credit expansion on the price
level. If, alternatively, the discrepancy is more typically attributable
to inflationist ideology, as Mises (1978a, pp. 134-38) came to believe,
then, in the absence of any fortuitous technological developments, the
credit expansion would put upward pressure on prices in general. Still,
this general rise in prices, this fall in the purchasing power of money,
is of less concern to the Austrians than the changes in relative prices
that result from the artificially low bank rate of interest.
The "tendencies" for reallocation
within the capital sector acknowledged by Wicksell become "actualities"
in the Austrian view. The market process is not so fail-safe as to preclude
any investment decision not consistent with the overall resource constraints.
Newly created money put into the hands of entrepreneurs at an artificially
low interest rate allows them to initiate production processes that eventually
conflict with the underlying economic realities (Hayek, 1967c, pp. 69-100).
Where Wicksell claimed that tendencies toward reallocation do not become
actualities, the Austrians claim that actual reallocations induced by credit
expansion are unsustainable. The artificial boom ends in a bust.
In his discussion of Keynesian
and Austrian concerns about interest-rate effects, Friedman claims that
the importance of ultimate effects, as compared to first-round effects,
is an empirical question (Gordon 1974, p. 147). The Austrians recognized
that ultimately, after boom, bust, and recovery, empirical analysis
would reveal no lingering effects of the initial credit expansion on the
bank rate of interest relative to the natural rate. The economy overall
would be less wealthy for having suffered a boom-bust cycle, and hence
the natural rate itself might well be higher. But the relative magnitudes
of the initial and ultimate effects is no basis for ignoring the market
process that produced them. The first-round effects constitute the initial
part of a market process that plays itself out within capital and resource
markets; the loss of wealth and possible increase in the natural rate is
the ultimate effect of that same market process.
The Dynamics of an Unsustainable Boom
Although Friedman does not engage in process analysis in his treatment
of the interest rate as it is affected by credit expansion, he does engage
in process analysis in his treatment of the wage rate as it is affected
by price-level inflation (Friedman, 1976, pp. 221-29). The first-round
effects consist of a discrepancy between two wage rates: the rate as perceived
by the workers and the rate as perceived by the employer. Such a discrepancy
occurs in the early phase of an inflation because the employer immediately
perceives the difference between the price he pays for labor and the newly
increased price of the one product he produces, while workers perceive,
but belatedly, the general increase in the prices they pay for consumer
goods The ultimate effect of price-level inflation is a rising nominal
wage rate, which maintains a real wage rate�as perceived (correctly) by
both employers and workers�consistent with the natural rate of unemployment.
Friedman could have made
the claim, in connection with these labor-market dynamics, that "the importance
of the ultimate effects in comparison to the first-round effects is an
empirical question." Undoubtedly, direct empirical testing�if data could
be obtained on the differing perceptions of wage rates�would show the ultimate
effects to be dominant. But Friedman does not dismiss his own analysis
with a rhetorical question about an empirical test. Instead, he sees the
first-round effects as the initial part of a market process that plays
itself out within labor markets, and he sees the reestablishment of the
natural rate of unemployment as the ultimate effect of that same process.
There is empirical evidence
consistent with both the Monetarist treatment of labor markets and the
Austrian treatment of credit markets. The unsustainablility of an inflation-induced
boom in labor markets and of a credit-induced boom in capital markets is
suggested by a natural rate of interest and a natural rate of unemployment
that are independent of monetary policy. Data on inflation rates and unemployment
rates for the last several decades must be accounted for in terms of some
market process through which monetary expansion has an initial effect,
but not a lasting one, on real magnitudes. Whether the most relevant market
process is one working through labor markets or one working through credit
markets is a matter of logical consistency, plausibility, and historical
relevance.(8) And, of course, Monetarist
labor-market dynamics and Austrian capital-market dynamics can be seen
as partial, complementary accounts of the same, more broadly conceived
market process.
This comparison of Monetarism
and Austrianism in the context of the dynamics of an unsustainable boom
seems to create an alliance between these two schools against Keynesianism.
The allied account of an artificial boom that contains the seeds of its
own destruction stands in contrast to the Keyensian account of a bust attributable
to a sudden and fundamentally unexplainable loss of confidence in the business
community. But the alliance is only a tactical one. Any theory of a boom-bust
cycle is inconsistent with Friedman's plucking model, which suggests that
there are no such cycles to be explained.
The original context in
which Friedman offered his account of the inflation-induced labor market
dynamics makes the inconsistency understandable. Friedman was not attempting
to identify a market process that fits neatly into his own Monetarism.
Instead, he was demonstrating the fallacy of a politically popular Keynesian
belief that there is a permanent trade-off between inflation and unemployment.
Based upon the empirical study done by A. W. Phillips in the late 1950s,
many Keynesians came to believe that the inverse relationship between rising
nominal wages and unemployment constituted a menu of social choices and
that policymakers should acknowledge the preferences of the electorate
by moving the economy to the most preferred combination of inflation and
unemployment.
Friedman was willing to
do battle with the Keynesian optimizers on their own turf. Accounting
for the inverse relationship in terms of a misperception of wages, he was
able to show that the alleged trade-off existed only in the short run and
therefore did not constitute a sound basis for policy prescription. There
is no evidence, however, that he considered these labor-market dynamics
to be an integral part of his own macroeconomics, although some Monetarists,
notably Edmund S. Phelps (1970), and most textbook writers have taken them
to be just that.(9) Neither Keynesianism,
as represented by ISLM analysis, nor Monetarism, as represented by Friedman's
plucking model, acknowledges the boom-bust cycle as a part of our macroeconomic
experience. Austrianism is set apart from the other two schools in this
regard. And, by adopting a fundamentally different framework at a lower
level of aggregation, the Austrians have been able to identify the capital-market
dynamics essential to the understanding of such cycles.
A Summary Assessment: The Wicksellian Watershed and the Austrian
Sieve
In the broad sweep of the history of macroeconomic thought, the Wicksellian
theme, in which there can be a temporary but significant discrepancy between
the bank rate and the natural rate of interest, constitutes an important
watershed. A significant portion of twentieth-century macroeconomics can
be categorized as variations of this Wicksellian theme. Included indisputably
in this category are followers of Wicksell in Sweden: Gustav Cassel, Eric
Lindahl, Bertil Ohlin, and Gunner Myrdal; Wicksell-inspired theorists in
Austria: Ludwig von Mises and, following him, F. A. Hayek; and British
theorists working in the tradition of the Currency school: Ralph Hawtrey,
Dennis Robertson, and taking his cue from the Austrians, the early Lionel
Robbins.
Excluded from this category
are those theorists who deny, ignore, or downplay the Wicksellian theme,
typically by adopting a level of macroeconomic aggregation too high for
that theme, in any of its variations, to emerge. Exemplifying these theorists
are Irving Fisher and, following him, Milton Friedman. Even Don Patinkin,
who draws heavily on Wicksell's ideas about the dynamics of price-level
adjustments, belongs to this group. His chosen level of aggregation, which
combines consumer goods and investment goods into a single aggregate called
commodities, precludes from the out set any non-trivial consequence of
the discrepancy between the bank rage and the natural rate.
Axel Leijonhufvud (1981,
p. 123) bases his own interpretation of Keynes on a similar grouping of
theorists. Wicksell and Fisher are at the headwaters of two separate traditions
labeled "Saving-Investment Theories" and "Quantity Theory." Leijonhufvud
makes Keynes out to be a Wicksellian, but he does so only by patching together
a new theory with ideas taken selectively from the Treatise and
the General Theory. This interpolation between Keynes's two books
is designated "Z-theory" (Ibid., pp. 164-69). Drawing from the first book,
it allows for a natural rate of interest from which the bank rate can diverge,
and
drawing from the second book, it allows for the resulting disequilibrium
to play itself out through quantity adjustments rather than through price
adjustments.
Leijonhufvud's hybrid Keynesian
theory gives play to the Wicksellian theme and fits comfortably in the
list of "Saving-Investment" theories. With the exposition of his "Z-theory,"
Leijonhufvud has clearly identified himself as a Wicksellian.(10)
To claim, however, that Keynes himself was a Wicksellian is to engage in
counter-factual doctrinal history. In the Treatise, the discrepancy
between the bank rate and the natural rate did not have a significant effect
on the saving-investment relationship; in the General Theory, significant
disturbances to the saving-investment relationship were not attributed
to a discrepancy between the two rates.
By offering his Z-theory
in support of Keynes's candidacy as a Wicksellian, Leijonhufvud tacitly
admits that Keynes had actually managed to skirt the Wicksellian idea first
on one side, then of the other. The categorization of theorists defended
in this chapter differs importantly from Leijonhufvud's in that Keynes
is transferred�on the basis of what he actually wrote�to the other side
of the Wicksellian watershed. Keynes's chosen level of aggregation, together
with his neglect of Wicksellian capital-market dynamics, establishes an
important kinship to Fisher, Friedman, and Patinkin.
Hayek's early "Reflections
on the Pure Theory of Money" might well have been entitled "Is Keynes a
Quantity Theorist?" Nearly half a century after his critique of the Treatise,
Hayek explicitly categorized "Keynes's economics as just another branch
of the centuries-old Quantity Theory school, the school now associated
with Milton Friedman" (Minard, 1979, p. 49). Keynes, according to Hayek,
"is a quantity theorist, but modified in an even more aggregative or collectivist
or macroeconomic tendency" (Ibid.).
The Wicksellian watershed,
as employed by Leijonhufvud, makes a first-order distinction between broad
categories of theories on the basis of subject matter. In one category,
the subject is saving and investment and the market process through which
these macroeconomic magnitudes are played off against one another. In the
other category, the subject is the quantity of money and the market process
through which changes in the supply of or demand for money affect other
real and nominal macroeconomic magnitudes.
An alternative first-order
distinction, more in the spirit of Hayek's critique of Keynes, is one based
on alternative levels of macroeconomic aggregation. The notion of a Wicksellian
watershed might well be supplemented by the notion of an Austrian sieve.
In one broad category of theories, the level of aggregation is low enough
to allow for a fruitful exploration of the Wicksellian theme. In the other
category, the level of aggregation is so high as to preclude any such exploration.
Based on their high levels of aggregation, then, both Keynesianism and
Monetarism fail to pass through the Austrian sieve. This is the meaning
of Hayek's claim that Keynes is a quantity theorist and of the corresponding
claim that Friedman is a Keynesian.
Bibliography (to be added)
Notes
1. This interpretation is almost universally
attributed to Hicks (on the basis of his early article) and to Hansen (on
the basis of his subsequent exposition). Warren Young (1987) makes the
case that, on the basis of the papers presented at the Oxford conference
in September 1936, credit for the ISLM formulation should be shared by
John Hicks, Roy Harrod, and James Meade.
2. Friedman clearly recognizes his
kinship to Keynes in terms of their fundamental approach: "I believe that
Keynes's theory is the right kind of theory in its simplicity, its concentration
of a few key magnitudes, its potential fruitfulness. I have been led to
reject it not on these grounds, but because I believe that it has been
contracted by experience" (Friedman, 1986, p. 48). Allan H. Meltzer identifies
the type of theorist that produces Keynes's kind of theory: "Keynes was
the type of theorist who developed his theory after he had developed a
sense of relative magnitudes and of the size and frequency of changes in
these magnitudes. He concentrated on those magnitudes that changed most,
often assuming that others remained fixed for the relevant period" (Meltzer,
1988, p. 18). This method is not as laudable as it may seem. If subtle
changes in credit and capital markets induce significant but difficult-to-perceive
changes in the economy's capital structure, then Keynes's�and Friedman's�method
is much too crude. Surely, the job of the economist is to identify market
processes even when�or especially when�the relevant market forces do not
have direct or immediate consequences for some macroeconomic aggregate.
3. Austrian macroeconomic relationships
are spelled out in various contexts by Ludwig von Mises (1966), F. A. Hayek,
(1967), Lionel Robbins (1934), Murray Rothbard (1970, 1983), Gerald P.
O'Driscoll, Jr. (1977), and Roger Garrison (1989, 1986).
4. The aphorism "the bigger the boom,
the bigger the bust" must be applied cautiously. The Austrian theory links
the necessary, or unavoidable, liquidation to the credit-induced misallocations.
It does not imply, as, for example, Gordon Tullock (1987) seems to believe,
that all the actual liquidation during the Great Depression is to be explained
with reference to misallocations that characterized the previous boom.
Much, if not most, of the liquidation during the 1930s can be attributed,
as Rothbard (1983) indicates, to misguided and perverse macroeconomic and
industrial policies implemented by the Hoover and Roosevelt administrations
5. The relative emphasis on secular
unemployment, as compared to cyclical unemployment, is consistent with
Meltzer's interpretation of Keynes (Meltzer, 1988, pp. 196-210). In most
modern textbooks, involuntary unemployment is taken to mean cyclical unemployment.
In Meltzer's view, which is more faithful to the General Theory
and to Keynes's long-held beliefs about capitalistic economies, cyclical
unemployment is a minor component of involuntary unemployment (Ibid.,
p. 126).
6. Although there is no explicit reference
to Hayek or other Austrian theorists in his article, the plucking model
is clearly intended as a basis for rejecting the general category of theories
which account for the boom-bust cycle.
7. It is recognized both by modern
Austrian theorists and by Wicksell's contemporaries that the equivalence
of the bank rate and the natural rate is consistent with price-level constancy
only in the special case of constant output. If the economy is experiencing
economic growth, then maintaining a saving-investment equilibrium will
put downward pressure on prices, and conversely, maintaining price-level
constancy will cause investment to run ahead of saving.
8. An assessment of the logical consistency,
plausibility, and historical relevance of these two perspectives on monetary
dynamics is undertaken in Bellante and Garrison (1988).
9. Friedman's Wicksell-styled analysis
of labor-market dynamics stands in direct conflict with his fourth-listed
Key Proposition of Monetarism, according to which "the changed rate of
growth of nominal income [induced by a monetary expansion] typically shows
up first in output and hardly at all in prices" (Friedman, 1970, p. 23).
In his subsequent Phillips curve analysis, misperceived price increases
precede
and are the proximate cause of increases in output. For an extended discussion
of this inconsistency, see Birch et al. (1982); for an attempt at
reconciliation, see Bellante and Garrison (1988, pp. 220-21).
10. But "Leijonhufvud the Wicksellian"
remains a puzzle to modern Austrian economists. In his exposition of the
Wicksellian theme, Leijonhufvud grafted Wicksell's credit-market dynamics
onto neoclassical capital theory and appended the following note: "Warning!
This is anachronistically put in terms of a much later literature on neoclassical
growth. Draining the Böhm-Bawerkian capital theory from Wicksell will
no doubt seem offensively impious to some, but I do not want to burden
this paper also with those complexities" (Leijonhufvud, 1981, p. 156).
Then, in his restatement of the critical arguments, Leijonhufvud reveals
his own judgment on natters of capital theory: "Like the Austrians,...I
would emphasize the heterogeneity of capital goods and the subjectivity
of entrepreneurial demand expectations." If Leijonhufvud had emphasized
Austrian capital theory as the stage on which the Wicksellian theme was
to be played out, he would have left Keynes in the wings and followed that
theme from Wicksell to Hayek.
|